Click here and press the right key for the next slide.
(This may not work on mobile or ipad. You can try using chrome or firefox, but even that may fail. Sorry.)
also ...
Press the left key to go backwards (or swipe right)
Press n to toggle whether notes are shown (or add '?notes' to the url before the #)
Press m or double tap to slide thumbnails (menu)
Press ? at any time to show the keyboard shortcuts
This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’
(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)
‘we should think of
meanings and beliefs
as interrelated constructs of a single theory
just as we already view
subjective values and probabilities
as interrelated constructs of decision theory’
(Davidson, 1974, p. 146)
why necessary?
will get to that later
habitual process
Action occurs in the presence of Stimulus.
Outcome follows action
Agent is rewarded
Stimulus-Action Link is strengthened due to reward
Given Stimulus, will Action occur? It depends on the strength of the Stimulus-Action Link.
‘goal-directed’ process
Action leads to Outcome.
Belief in Action-Outcome link is strengthened.
Agent has a Desire for the Outcome
Will Action occur? It depends on the Belief in the Action-Outcome Link and Agent’s Desire.
This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’
(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)
cannot infer preferences unless we know subjective probabilities
‘the revealed preference revolution of the 1930s (Samuelson, 1938)
... replaced the supposition that people are attempting to optimize any externally given criterion (e.g., some psychologically interpretable motion of utility, perhaps to be quantified in units of pleasure and pain).
Chater (2014)
‘Suppose that A and B are consequences between which the agent is not indifferent, and that N is an ethically neutral condition [i.e. the agent is indifferent between N and not N].
Then N has probability 1/2 if and only if the agent is indifferent between the following two gambles:
1. B if N, A if not
2. A if N, B if not’
(Jeffrey, 1983, p. 47)
What have we done?
Your actions are a function of two things,
subjective probabilities
and preferences.
Ramsey’s method allows us to
infer both of these
from observations of the actions you perform
plus some background assumptions (axioms).
But what did we assume in characterising preferences?
transitivity
For any A, B, C ∈ S: if A⪯B and B⪯C then A⪯C.
completeness
For any A, B ∈ S: either A⪯B or B⪯A
continuity
‘Continuity implies that no outcome is so bad that you would not be willing to take some gamble that might result in you ending up with that outcome [...] provided that the chance of the bad outcome is small enough.’
independence
roughly, if you prefer A to B then you should prefer A and C to B and C.
Steele & Stefánsson (2020, p. §2.3)
things the theory
assumes
actions
outcomes
+ some axioms (background assumptions)
things the theory characterises
preference
subjective probability
rationality (?!)
This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’
(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)
The axioms can be regarded as implicitly defining
preference
and
subjective probability.
More carefully,
preference and subjective probability
are constructs of decision theory.
This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’
(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)
‘we should think of
meanings and beliefs
as interrelated constructs of a single theory
just as we already view
subjective values and probabilities
as interrelated constructs of decision theory’
(Davidson, 1974, p. 146)
why necessary?
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
Is
folk psychology
a source of common knowledge of principles
that implicitly define ‘intention’, ‘knowledge’, and the rest
?
Lewis (1972) vs Heider (1958)
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
functions of everyday mindreading expertise:
normative
ethical
legal
self-regulative (aspirational)
predictive -- speed-accuracy trade-offs
...
As philosophers see
folk psychology ...
‘When someone is in so-and-so combination of mental states and receives sensory stimuli of so-and-so kind, he tends with so-and-so probability to be caused thereby to go into so-and-so mental states and produce so-and-so motor responses.’
(Lewis, 1972, p. 256)
(my|your|his|her|their) phone
is trying to (excluding ‘kill me’) [283,000]
wants to [278,000]
hates [147,000]
likes [86,800]
thinks (e.g. ‘My phone thinks I’m in another city’) [53,400]
is pretending [16,000]
Is
folk psychology
a source of common knowledge of principles
that implicitly define ‘intention’, ‘knowledge’, and the rest
?
Lewis (1972) vs Heider (1958)
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
obstacle: diversity , inter- and intra-personal
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
obstacle: diversity , inter- and intra-personal
option 2: philosophical
KNOWLEDGE | yes | no |
Is it a mental state? | Williamson (2000) | Hyman (1999) |
Knowing entails believing? | Rose & Schaffer (2013) | Radford (1966) |
Is it a form of belief? | Sosa (2007) | Williamson (2000) |
Valuable for action? | Plato’s Meno | Kaplan (1985) |
Is humanly attainable? | [others] | Unger (1975) |
Depends on context? | Lewis (1996) | [lots] |
Which things manifest agency?
‘The paramecium’s swimming through the beating of its cilia, in a coordinated way, and perhaps its initial reversal of direction, count as agency.’
(Burge, 2009, p. 259)
‘the paramecium cannot be an agent [...]
None of its interactions with the environment [...] need involve anything like an act on the part of the paramecium.’
(Steward, 2009, p. 227)
Do these two have a shared understanding of agency?
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
obstacle: diversity , inter- and intra-personal
option 2: philosophical
obstacle: diversity
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
obstacle: diversity , inter- and intra-personal
option 2: philosophical
obstacle: diversity
obstacle: n’ting good anchors philosophers’ understandings
Philosophical Folk Psychology
‘epistemic case intuitions are generated by [...] folk psychology’
Nagel (2012, p. 510)
‘some part of us finds it almost impossible not to categorise them as’ agents
Steward (2009, p. 229)
Philosophical accounts of minds and actions ...
... anchor a shared understanding of what knowledge, belief, joy and the rest are.
... could be (mis)used to characterise various models of mind.
Why do we need decision theory to characterise belief and desire?
option 1: pre-theoretic (‘intuitive’) grounding
defence: folk psychology as expertise
obstacle: diversity , inter- and intra-personal
option 2: philosophical
obstacle: diversity
obstacle: n’ting good anchors philosophers’ understandings
option 3: formal (use decision theory)
obstacle: ...
This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’
(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)
‘we should think of
meanings and beliefs
as interrelated constructs of a single theory
just as we already view
subjective values and probabilities
as interrelated constructs of decision theory’
(Davidson, 1974, p. 146)
why necessary?
for shared understanding!
so far ...
1. We understand what decision theory is
2. and how it can be used to provide us as researchers with a shared understanding of belief and desire.
3. This is necessary because not folk psychology, nor intuition nor philosophy provide a shared understanding.
next: relation to the dual-process theory of instrumental action
4. If that theory is true, agents disobey axioms of decision theory.